Buy Study Guide
Summary
Kant acknowledges that it is difficult to distinguish examples of anyone acting from pure duty. In fact, this is why philosophers have ignored this aspect of human life, and ascribed all moral behavior to self-love. With any example, it’s impossible to definitively state that self-love didn’t sneak in as a motivator.
Kant concedes that most human actions are in accordance with duty. But it is still doubtful if true virtue is to be found in the world. But that doesn’t change the facts of moral judgment. Just because there are no completely sincere people in the world, doesn’t mean that sincerity isn’t morally worthy.
We also have to observe that moral judgments have to be true and universal for all rational beings, not just us in a particular situation, with absolute necessity. Thus, it is nearly impossible for any example to serve as truly moral. That doesn’t mean that morality isn’t thinkable, but rather that examples are a faulty methodological tool for a moral philosophy.
We only know what goodness is because we have an idea of it, and we can only be good insofar as we follow that idea. This idea is what a moral philosophy has to work out. It can’t simply be a collection of instructive examples, since these will necessarily be jumbled, without any ultimate coherence.
Thus, all moral concepts have their ground in reason. By adding empirical examples to them, one actually lessens their instructive importance. And what’s more, a moral philosophy, therefore, has to derive its notions of morality from man’s being a rational being as such. Otherwise, their effect will be mixed, and they’ll have no genuinely instructive value.
Everything in nature works according to the law. Only a rational being—one that can go beyond what is empirically present and posit universal laws—can act in accordance with laws. Only rational beings have wills, since will is simply practical reason—reason applied to practical situations.
That will is necessarily our own. We can't refer to some external power, like God, as justification. Divine will can’t be the basis for our own action; there’s no higher force that tells us to do things. (For example, we can't justify actions as moral by referring them to a "conscience" through which the voice of God speaks).
Now, how do we know that the will is choosing rationally? For reason to adequately determine the will, the will has to choose to do what reason determines as objectively necessary. The will must recognize this objective necessity as subjectively necessary—something that I must do, in a concrete, specific situation. When this does not happen, the will acts according to grounds that are subjective, and therefore contingent, and cannot be characterized as universal and therefore morally worthy. Necessity corresponds with morality.
Kant calls the representation (the appearance in the mind) of an objective principle an imperative. Imperatives are expressed by an ought—“I ought to do this”—rather than a thought like "it would be pleasant or advantageous to me to do this.” Our will isn’t always determined by an imperative. Sometimes we do things simply because they would be agreeable. But when the will is determined by an imperative, it is determined objectively—that is, we feel that our action would be valid for everyone.
Now, Kant goes on to explain how imperatives work, and the different kinds of imperatives. It's important to understand these distinctions to see how, exactly, the categorical imperative works, and what its scope is.
All imperatives are either hypothetical or categorical. Hypotheticals are a means of achieving something else that is willed. ("If I do X, Y will happen.") A categorical imperative is objectively necessary in itself. ("Y will happen.") Since the practical law is a way of considering actions as possible goods, a hypothetical is an action that is good as a means to something; but a categorical imperative is good in itself.
The hypothetical imperative can be a means to a possible or actual purpose. If it is directed towards a possible purpose, chosen by preference and attained by skill, it is problematic hypothetical. (For example: "if you want to get better at the piano, practice.") These imperatives make no judgments about the value of the end in question, only the fitness of the means to the end.
An assertoric hypothetical imperative, on the other hand, is directed towards an end that everyone recognizes as good—happiness, the desire for which we recognize as universally human. Assertoric hypothetical imperatives make individual judgments about the best way to reach this end. (For example: "if you want to be happy, eat a bar of chocolate.")
In the case of the former, the objectivity is applied only to the means, but not to consideration of the end. In the latter, objectivity is applied to the end, but not the means. The first are rules of skill, the second are counsels of prudence.
The first case—problematic judgments—involve judgments of skill. Whoever wills the goal, also wills the best means to get there. The means are just deduced from the end in itself; they are for all intents one and the same. Getting good at the piano and practicing are, from the standpoint of the will, identical.
With assertoric hypotheticals, it’s more complicated, since we don’t know exactly what happiness is, and what it means to “will” it. These concepts have to be borrowed from experience. Happiness is an absolute state, but as a finite being, I can’t know exactly what it is; I can only will things I think might make me happy, without being sure that they will do so. Thus, they can’t be practically necessary, they can only be provisional suggestions. In principle, though, it is the same as an imperative of skill—the only difference being that here the end is possible, instead of actual.
But categorical imperatives are different from both of these. In contrast to hypothetical imperatives, they make no judgments about means and ends. They concern things that are goods in themselves. Only these judgments, Kant argues, are truly moral. The categorical imperative is not a kind of advice, but an objective judgment that a rational being applies to itself.
It’s the categorical imperative—morality—that Kant wants to get to the bottom of. Unlike the others, we know that we can’t get to it empirically, by means of examples. The worry, then, is that categoricals might secretly be hypotheticals—that we might be justifying them with judgments of skill or means that we smuggle in below the radar. “You shouldn’t deceive other people”—we assume that we are making a categorical judgment by avoiding reference to a specific situation, but we still can’t show that there isn’t secretly an incentive at work. (Like: “...Or else you’ll be exposed as a liar.")
Because we can’t rely on examples, the possibility of a priori moral judgments, i.e., categorical imperatives, will have to be grounded a priori as well, without reference to specific examples. For the same reason, there is in fact only one categorical imperative: to act in such a way that the maxim by which you act can be the basis for a universal law.
Kant goes on to consider four situations in which the categorical imperative might be applied. The first is suicide, in the case when of a person has become miserable. That cannot be a law, since it cannot be a law of nature for everyone to kill themselves. The second is someone who is destitute, who considers borrowing money but never paying it back. That can’t be the basis for a universal law, because then there would be no lending ever, and the person's action wouldn't be possible in the first place. The third is a person with a talent who is nonetheless comfortable. He has a duty to cultivate his talent, because if no one cultivated their talent, the human race would languish entirely. The fourth example, is a person who never borrows money, and therefore never lends it either. But that could not be the basis for a universal law, because a person who did that would forgo of ever getting assistance when he himself had need of it.
Thus, individuals are involved in a contradiction in each example. They accept the validity of the law, but they think that, in their specific case, it doesn’t apply. If they referred to the categorical imperative, they would see how they should change their ways.
Analysis
The reader will likely have noticed that the second part of the Groundwork takes a noticeable jump in difficulty and complexity. Kant’s task now is to work out just how acting in accordance with the moral law works, given the arguments about the human mind that Kant worked out in the Critique of Pure Reason. Here, we get a more abstract philosophical argument, one that relies much more heavily on technical philosophical terminology.
Kant’s goal in the first half of the second part is to show that acting as though your action could be the basis for a universal law is the only possible basis for morality. Because morality is based on a universal law, we cannot argue from examples, for the obvious reason that examples only furnish individual cases—never a universal code of conduct. Therefore, we will have to be able to make this argument by examining the structure of our mind, and the role that our will plays in our determining our actions, and not by using common sense examples.
In this respect, Kant’s moral philosophy is an obvious corollary to questions about the mind that Kant explored in the Critique of Pure Reason. There, Kant’s question was how it was possible to know anything at all. He argued that objective knowledge was possible because, though every person has unique sensory impressions, our minds all combined these impressions in the same way to make objective statements. “This table is brown” is a subjective judgment, and when we make it, we allow for the possibility that someone (someone color blind, for example), might disagree. But when we say, “This table is brown because I just saw someone paint it that color,” we expect every other rationally thinking person to agree. Kant believes that this argument solves the question of how knowledge—and science—are possible, despite the fact that every person experiences the world differently.
The categorical imperative works in much the same way. Moral judgments, to be truly moral and not just expedient, have to be necessary; that is, they have to be as self-evidently and universally true as the statement that 2+2=4. Therefore, they make a much stronger claim than a statement like, “It was justified for me to steal a loaf of bread because I was hungry.” We can easily imagine that, from the perspective of the bakery owner, this statement does not hold water. Moral laws need to be true for everyone.
Kant adds another dimension to this in the consideration of means and ends, which will become more important in the second half of the chapter. All of our practical reasoning is a way of thinking that matches means to ends. We can think of judgments where the ultimate value of the goal is up for debate, but the means are universally acknowledged. (“If you want to get better at baseball, practice your swing every day.") We can also imagine judgments where the value of the goal is universal, but where the means are up for debate. (“If you want to be happy, eat a sandwich.”) The categorical imperative is the only one in which both the means and the ends are universally acknowledged.
But the larger function of the categorical imperative is to resolve Kant’s belief that the individual must be his own guide with his belief that thought and human life only have meaning because they take place in a community. The categorical imperative pulls us out of the contingency and inconstancy of our individual experience, and force us to imagine ourselves as belonging to a community of rational subjects. (We will learn more about that in the second half of this section.) But isn’t that what the church does? Or school? Or our parents? Implicit in the categorical imperative is that only the human mind is the legitimate moral authority, and that it saves itself from isolation and solipsism (the belief that all other people are just a figment of our imagination) by positing its actions as the basis for the universal law.
The main difficulty posed by the categorical imperative is, of course, how we choose to read the situations in which we apply it. If I were debating whether to steal bread to feed my family, I could reasonably argue that I was following the imperative to always do good for one’s loved ones, no matter the danger to myself. In having me arrested, the baker could also reasonably claim that he was following his imperative to fulfilling his potential by protecting his business, as well as the livelihoods of his employees, and further preserving the order of the law, similarly to the argument in the third and fourth examples that Kant gives. It is an unquestioned assumption in Kant that all rational people will come to the same conclusion if they think rationally.
But the most serious attack on the categorical imperative was launched by the late-nineteenth-century philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche. Nietzsche rejects out of hand the notion that morality, or, for that matter, philosophy, must be universal. The goal of Nietzsche’s morals, or rather, his critique of them, is to show that the purpose of philosophy and thought is to emphasize one’s difference from others, not the universal similarities; indeed, to luxuriate in this difference. Thought and reality are multi-faceted and contradictory; a “universal morality” was just a symptom of the inability to embrace the hard truth that there is no truth, that good and evil are ultimately flexible constructs. This view has ultimately predominated in contemporary philosophy and critical theory, which reject the notion of a common human mind on which Kant’s morality is based.
FAQs
What is the analysis of Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals? ›
Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals summary shows how acting out of respect for the categorical imperative and in conformity with it is the only route to acting rationally and autonomously. Autonomy means "freedom" in the sense of being self-determined.
What happened in chapter 1 of metaphysics? ›Chapter 1. In Chapter 1 of Book A Aristotle states that all people by nature desire to know, or desire understanding. He then discusses a number of different kinds of thing that we might seek in order to satisfy this desire.
What are the two distinct parts of the book metaphysics of moral? ›The Metaphysics of Morals (German: Die Metaphysik der Sitten) is a 1797 work of political and moral philosophy by Immanuel Kant. It is divided into two sections: the Doctrine of Right, dealing with political rights, and the Doctrine of Virtue, dealing with ethical virtues.
What is Kant's main point? ›Kant's main goal is to show that a critique of reason by reason itself, unaided and unrestrained by traditional authorities, establishes a secure and consistent basis for both Newtonian science and traditional morality and religion.
What is the main theme of metaphysics? ›Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, including the first principles of: being or existence, identity and change, space and time, cause and effect, necessity, and possibility.
What is metaphysics and what questions does it seek to answer? ›The study of reality and existence is metaphysics, named from a set of books written by Aristotle asking what is being, what are first causes, and what is change. It studies what we are and what our purpose is, seeking knowledge about everything from the nature of the entire universe to that of the human mind.
What is the simplest explanation of metaphysics? ›Derived from the Greek meta ta physika ("after the things of nature"); referring to an idea, doctrine, or posited reality outside of human sense perception. In modern philosophical terminology, metaphysics refers to the studies of what cannot be reached through objective studies of material reality.
What is the summary of metaphysics? ›metaphysics, Branch of philosophy that studies the ultimate structure and constitution of reality—i.e., of that which is real, insofar as it is real.
What are the two main questions of metaphysics? ›The Big Metaphysical Questions
What is consciousness? Does the world really exist?
Peirce divided metaphysics into (1) ontology or general metaphysics, (2) psychical or religious metaphysics, and (3) physical metaphysics.
What is the meaning of metaphysics of morals? ›
Description. The Metaphysics of Morals is Kant's final major work in moral philosophy. In it, he presents the basic concepts and principles of right and virtue and the system of duties of human beings as such.
What is the metaphysical versus the man made summary? ›Any natural phenomenon, i.e., any event which occurs without human participation, is the metaphysically given, and could not have occurred differently or failed to occur; any phenomenon involving human action is the man-made, and could have been different.
What are the three 3 points in Kant reason? ›Kant proposes three questions that answer “all the interest of my reason”: “What can I know?” “What must I do?” and “What may I hope?” (A805/B833).
What are the 2 main principles of Kant explain? ›Here are two formulation of Kant's Categorical Imperative: CIa: Always treat persons (including yourself) and ends in themselves, never merely as a means to your own ends. CIb: Act only on that maxim that you can consistently will to be a universal law.
What are three key points from the ethical theory of Kant? ›This essay will discuss three main characteristics of Kant's ethical theory - namely, the universal maxim, the categorical imperative and the importance of a good will.
What is the conclusion of metaphysics? ›Metaphysics reveals such principles and ends as it ensures that those principles are not separated from reality. Only metaphysics as it is classically understood investigates reality precisely as reality.
What are the 4 components of metaphysics explain? ›(He had four names for the branch of philosophy that is the subject-matter of Metaphysics: 'first philosophy', 'first science', 'wisdom', and 'theology'.)
Why is metaphysics important in everyday life? ›Metaphysics adds a level of conceptual rigor and clarity that can only improve the steadfastness of our knowledge: it is not here to compete with or replace any other fields, it is here as a necessary supplement to them in our quest for truth about reality.
Why is the question of metaphysics important? ›Metaphysics is one of the most ancient and important branches of philosophy, it is the study of the concepts that are beyond the sensible experience, empirical justifications, and physics; it aims to study the fundamental nature as a thing in itself, beyond what is tangible.
What are the examples of metaphysical issues? ›Typical issues include transcendence, being, existence in its individual and communal dimensions, causality, relations, analogy, purpose, the possibility of metaphysics, and the relations of metaphysics to other disciplines.
Why is metaphysics hard to understand? ›
Thus, knowledge of the most universal things must be the most difficult knowledge. But metaphysics considers the most universal principles, the principles that must be true of all reality. Therefore, metaphysics is the most difficult thing to study.
What are the first principles of metaphysics? ›The first metaphysical principles of every created being, those by which it is constituted, are potentiality and actuality. -- Every created being was, before its existence, in the series of possible beings; it had only a possibility to exist; it was in potentiality. Afterward it existed; then it was in actuality.
What is a simple example of metaphysics? ›Examples of metaphysical concepts are Being, Existence, Purpose, Universals, Property, Relation, Causality, Space, Time, Event, and many others. They are fundamental, because all other concepts and beliefs rest on them. All Knowledge and Value is based upon the definitions of these concepts.
Who summarized metaphysics? ›Plot Summary. Metaphysics is a major work of philosophy by the Classical Greek writer and philosopher Aristotle, considered one of his principal works and the first major work of philosophy within the field.
What is the most contentious question of metaphysics? ›David Hume (1711–1776) described the question of liberty and necessity as 'the most contentious question of metaphysics, the most contentious science' (Hume [1748] 1975, p. 95). He was right about it being contentious. Whether it is metaphysical is another matter.
How long is Kant's metaphysics of morals? ›A defining work of moral philosophy, Kant's Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals has been influential to an extent far beyond what its modest length (roughly 75 pages) might suggest. It is also a famously difficult work, concerned with propounding universal principles rather than answering practical questions.
What is belief in the metaphysical? ›At the very heart of a religion such as Christianity there stands a metaphysical belief in a reality that is alleged to transcend the empirical world. It is the metaphysical belief that there is an eternal, ever-present creative source and sustainer of the universe.
Why is man a metaphysical being? ›The metaphysics of man can be defined as a place of meeting of the individual and the universal, as a unity of generic, social, and personal levels of human being.
What does Eliot want to conclude about the metaphysical poets? ›Eliot quotes Johnson's line about metaphysical poetry that 'the most heterogeneous ideas are yoked by violence together'. Eliot's response to Johnson's censure, however, is to point out that all kinds of poets – not just the metaphysicals – unite heterogeneous or different materials together in their poetry.
What is Plato's main metaphysical theory? ›
Platonism is the view that there exist such things as abstract objects — where an abstract object is an object that does not exist in space or time and which is therefore entirely non-physical and non-mental.
Does Kant believe in God? ›In a work published the year he died, Kant analyzes the core of his theological doctrine into three articles of faith: (1) he believes in one God, who is the causal source of all good in the world; (2) he believes in the possibility of harmonizing God's purposes with our greatest good; and (3) he believes in human ...
What is the famous line of Immanuel Kant? ›All our knowledge begins with the senses, proceeds then to the understanding, and ends with reason. There is nothing higher than reason.
What is Kantian theory in simple terms? ›In brief, Kant's moral philosophy focuses on fairness and the value of the individual. His method rests on our ability to reason, our autonomy (i.e. our ability to give ourselves moral law and govern our own lives), and logical consistency.
What is Kantian ethics for dummies? ›Kantianism emphasizes the principles behind actions rather than an action's results. Acting rightly thus requires being motivated by proper universal principles that treat everyone with respect. When you're motivated by the right principles, you overcome your animal instincts and act ethically.
What is the summary of Kantianism? ›Kantianism , System of critical philosophy created by Immanuel Kant and the philosophies that have arisen from the study of his writings. Kantianism comprises diverse philosophies that share Kant's concern to explore the nature and limits of human knowledge in the hope of raising philosophy to the level of a science.
What is an example of Kant's ethics in real life? ›Kant argued that we have an obligation to sometimes help out others in need. To help people out is to make their ends our ends. For example, if you see that someone is poor and hungry, his end at that point might be to get food. If you give him food or money to buy food, you are making it your end to feed him.
What is metaphysical analysis? ›Metaphysical studies generally seek to explain inherent or universal elements of reality which are not easily discovered or experienced in our everyday life. As such, it is concerned with explaining the features of reality that exist beyond the physical world and our immediate senses.
What does Nietzsche mean by metaphysics? ›Metaphysics: is a theory that has the claim to ask questions and provide answers beyond our available knowledge. It is objected that even for asking questions, a knowledge of the meanings of the words used is required.
What are some important quotes from Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals? ›“Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.” “Innocence is a splendid thing, only it has the misfortune not to keep very well and to be easily misled.” “Enlightenment is man's release from his self incurred tutelage.
What studies the meaning of moral language and the metaphysics of moral facts? ›
Normative ethics is distinct from Meta ethics because it examines standards for the rightness and the wrongness of actions, while Meta ethics studies the meaning of moral language and the metaphysics of moral facts.
What are the 3 metaphysical questions? ›The Big Metaphysical Questions
What is our place in the universe? What is consciousness? Does the world really exist?
In his works, Nietzsche questioned the basis of good and evil. He believed that heaven was an unreal place or “the world of ideas”. His ideas of atheism were demonstrated in works such as “God is dead”. He argued that the development of science and emergence of a secular world were leading to the death of Christianity.
What are Nietzsche's main beliefs? ›Nietzsche claimed the exemplary human being must craft his/her own identity through self-realization and do so without relying on anything transcending that life—such as God or a soul.
What is God in metaphysics? ›'God' becomes a subject of metaphysics because God is a being. Of all possible subjects of metaphysics 'God' supposits for the most perfect and thus is afforded the position of the first subject of metaphysics by the pri- macy of perfection. 'God' is, of course, also the subject of theology.
What is a famous quote about metaphysics? ›- “The investigation of the truth is in one way hard, in another easy.” ...
- “So while a thing in a finite time cannot come in contact with things quantitatively infinite, it can come in contact with things infinite in respect of divisibility: for in this sense the time itself is also infinite.”
Given that the moral law, if it exists, is universal and necessary, the only appropriate means to investigate it is through a priori rational reflection. Thus, a correct theoretical understanding of morality requires a metaphysics of morals.
What is Kant's moral theory based on his book Foundation of the Metaphysics of Morals? ›Kant argued that the moral law is a truth of reason, and hence that all rational creatures are bound by the same moral law. Thus in answer to the question, “What should I do?” Kant replies that we should act rationally, in accordance with a universal moral law.
What is the theory of moral understanding? ›Kohlberg's theory of moral development is a theory that focuses on how children develop morality and moral reasoning. Kohlberg's theory suggests that moral development occurs in a series of six stages and that moral logic is primarily focused on seeking and maintaining justice.